Historically, the formation of law, but also the differentiation of jurisdiction, took place over long phases without a pronounced manorial monopoly of power, which only emerged successively in the course of state-building processes, but which repeatedly experienced new forms of limitation precisely as a result of territorial expansion processes. Although there was no lack of power relations (for example in the context of family structures, as an effect of unequally distributed economic resources or with regard to gender relations), these were not organised in such a way that they could have centralised law-making and law enforcement. Nevertheless, standardisation efforts can be identified at all times – but they were not necessarily initiated and enforced by means of power and domination. One can think here of forms of standardisation through academisation (e.g. the spread of Roman law in Europe through university legal training), through informal forms of legal transplant (e.g. in the case of the voluntary adoption of policey regulations within city networks or imperial circles in the Holy Roman Empire) or simply through the regular demand of courts as structures for offering conflict resolution (empowering interactions). However, such 'voluntary' demand was by no means arbitrary; rather, different power relations played a role here too, for example in the question of which forums were or could be called upon by whom and in which cases. These power relations also raise the question of which groups benefit from certain forms of legal standardisation and who benefits from forms of legalpluralism. As a rule, no generalising statements can be made about complex social constellations, because the answer varies depending on the point of observation: for example, indigenous groups that invoke international law against hegemonic legal standardisation may well benefit from forms of legal pluralisation, for example with regard to possibilities of land use, while women or minorities in these groups may at the same time be legally disadvantaged.
Standardisation as a demand effect can also be observed in the case of legal norms whose application by the respective courts could not be enforced for a long time (especially when it came to corporately organised courts). In this way, the medieval supreme court system was able to create comparatively stable legal circles, as so-called mother cities based their ius fori on the answers to questions from their daughter cities. This never had anything to do with political claims to power or territorial borders, and yet it was a way of striving for regional legal unity. By translating customary law sources into Slavic languages, for example, it was even possible to overcome ethnic boundaries in this way. The prerequisite for such a right was, of course, a minimum degree of voluntariness. If this consensus collapsed, uniform legal structures across the region were hardly conceivable (as was the case with the decline of the Feme in the late 15th century). In any case, state-centred concepts of law often prove to be outdated in historical retrospect. Law without rule or without a monopoly on power must therefore not be lost in historical comparison, and the border areas between law and other forms of normativity must also be kept in view. It has proven to be important to examine questions of unity and plurality not only in the context of state-building processes, but also to take a more overarching approach and ask much more openly about patterns and constellations of power relations to be found in specific situations and their effects on forms of legal unification or the organisation of plurality in law. In the second funding phase, we will expand and deepen the reflections on these connections that we began in the first phase of the programme.
Furthermore, with regard to structures of power in the past and present, it must be emphasised that the discussion about claims to unity begins with the question of which groups and spaces have been used by those in power to assert and enforce their respective claims to power. For a long time, the content of law and the respective geographical extent of sovereign territories were not congruent. On the one hand, the formation of law through custom and supra-regional courts could lead to comparatively uniform law above small-scale sovereign claims. At the same time, small-scale solutions that tended to be detached from political power structures are known in family property law, for example, which created different laws from village to village, indeed from house number to house number. On the other hand, the attractiveness of an orderly and, in view of the reduction of transaction costs, more predictable judicial settlement of conflicts should not be underestimated and led to standardisation, for example when legally exempt groups such as Armenians in cities of late medieval Poland voluntarily submitted to the German courts without pressure from the authorities, because this seemed useful for their trading activities.
In applicable law, there are fruitful parallels to the historical perspective in the inter- and transnational area. International law is not only fragmented into various regimes, each of which pursues its own regulatory claims and logic and has no hierarchical relationship to one another, so that in extreme cases regime collisions can occur in overlapping areas of application. In many cases, it also lacks coercive enforcement mechanisms, which is why it is dependent on being implemented in the respective local or national contexts. Particularly in the area of universal human rights, i.e. treaties that are not regionally limited, this always means a transposition of the common norms into legal ‘dialects’; it is therefore a matter of ‘translating human rights into the vernacular’ (Sally Engle Merry, Human Rights and Gender Violence, Chicago 2006). This also applies to the Council of Europe, which, in the European Court of Human Rights (ECHR), has a body that can make legally binding judgements, issue interim injunctions and even award damages. With the margin of appreciation, the ECHR has developed a form of tolerance of ambiguity for national particularities, which makes it possible to allow diversity in particularly controversial areas of law or in fields of particularly diverse practice without having to forego common minimum human rights standards. Although a common legal norm is applied, which cannot actually have several meanings at the same time, an integration of unavoidable plurality is thus achieved.
Much like in pre-modern contexts, a claim to standardisation in international law can hope less for top-down enforcement than for long-term processes of increasing norm acceptance and harmonisation, while at the same time – similar to imperial legal systems – living with a certain degree of pluralism for an indefinite period of time, perhaps forever. This follows from the fact that ‘local’ (national) law will not be reached everywhere in its deeper layers.
Based on this aspect, it can be formulated as a working hypothesis for the formation of types in the second phase that the relationship between unity and plurality plays a similar role in each case where standardisation cannot be enforced qua monopoly of power and specific forms of standardisation that are remote from power therefore occur in the legal systems. Subsequently, the question arises as to how plurality can be made manageable if all relevant rules have to be formed and enforced without enforcement authority.